Heidegger discusses four different ways in which the word
“world” has been used. The first definition is that of traditional philosophy,
“'World' is used as an ontical concept, and signifies the totality of those
entities which can be present-at-hand within the world” (BT 93/65). Traditional
philosophy has only investigated the present-at-hand objects within the world. They
view the world as a set of undifferentiated things – matter or stuff -- situated
within objective space. By present-at-hand,
Heidegger means objects that are immediately present to consciousness. Put more
abstrusely: specific equipment or tools which have been yanked (de-worlded)
from the totality of equipment and thus become self-contained or looked at in
isolation by Dasein (human beings). In the present-at-hand mode of Being,
equipment remains unused during observation. By observing the present-at-hand
Dasein inevitably enters into a detached theoretical/philosophical/scientific
mode of Being. Think the scientist who just neutrally observes by staring and
watching what an object does.
Traditionally
philosophy conceptualized space as a system of physical distance: light years,
inches, feet, etc. Human beings were depicted as existing within a box-like
universe populated by a system of objects or aggregate of things. Humans
interact with objects and other humans in a three dimensional world. Dasein
experiences itself as distinct and separate from the world and others. The way
of viewing the world relies upon the conception of substantatility that takes
the world as consisting of an internal (subjective, mind) and external
(objective, world) – thus leading to a pseudo-problem of how the internal
(human subjectivity) is able to interact and truly comprehend the external
world. Entities have a common empirical features; this however does not
constitute the essence of the world. By accepting the subject/object dichotomy,
philosophy necessarily ignores the question of Being in general; it ignores the
ontological, and focuses on the ontic.
Starting
with entities, as opposed to Being, led philosophers to adopt a subject/object
mode of viewing the world, because of this the being of the world is
presupposed before investigation of the world begins. According to Heidegger, ontologically
Dasein does not experience the world as present-at-hand, i.e. in a detached,
theoretical manner. Phenomenologically Dasein is not located in space-time,
grappling with objects in mere thought only. Heidegger dismisses traditional
philosophy's view of the world. Dasein's primary relation to the world is one
of use, not just thinking about
physical objects distinct from Dasein.
What briefly shows itself is the structure of
presence-at-hand, which philosophy has failed to grasp. Heidegger points to the
inherent structural or methodological problem of theoretical observation when he states,
No matter how sharply we just look at the ‘outward appearance’ of
Things in whatever form this takes, we cannot discover anything
ready-to-hand. If we look at things just
‘theoretically,’ we can get along without understanding readiness to hand. (BT
98/69).
Heidegger is able to capture the
phenomena ignored by other philosophers by giving a phenomenological
description of the world. By
investigating the ready-to-hand Heidegger points out that that which is closest
is ontologically furthest away. For instance, one's glasses are ontically
close, yet one never even takes note of them unless they malfunction by
breaking or digging into the skin. What briefly shows itself is the structure
of presence-at-hand. One quickly notices
that Heidegger does not talk about subjects or minds, but of Dasein. The
world and Dasein are a unified whole, both are inseparably merged together.
When one is playing baseball, for example, it is almost as if the glove is
indistinguishable from Dasein. In the experience of catching the ball, one does
not think of the glove as an entity apart from the body, but as an extension of
the whole. Equipment and Dasein come together forming an undifferentiated mass,
the experience of playing baseball.
Heidegger refers to Dasein's engaged interactions with the
world as “dealings.” Heidegger points out that humans live in the world
and experience the world as familiar. Dasein's familiarity with the
world is with places. By places, it is meant an area or space (not in the
physical sense) which Dasein feels a sense of ownership and concern towards the
world. Dasein is familiar with the world, it knows its way around it. The
world, in this sense, is a concrete experiential context -- as opposed to a
physical-spatial context -- wherein Dasein is immersed or surrounded. In other
words, Dasein's concernful interaction with the entities in the world is
characterized by the fact that the objects in the world matter to Dasein. For
instance, while watching a movie one cares about being in an environment
conducive to viewing a film: dimmed lights, a comfortable seat, etc. These
entities matter, they have significance for Dasein; however, the reverse is not
true. A chair does not posses and sense of ownership, nor does it care about
the aura of the room. Entities do not do anything by themselves: they don't act
upon the world, nor do they have a sense of concern for the world or a sense
of “mineness.”Equipment merely sits
idle, unless Dasein engages with it.
Dasein's
engagement with equipment is purposeful; this points to the nature of equipment
as ready-to-hand. All equipment is used for
a purpose, or a “for-the-sake-of-which.” One important feature of
readiness-to-hand (the type of being which belongs to equipment) is that it
withdraws. During use, the tool itself
withdraws from our thematic observation, our awareness. Tools do not withdraw
when being observed, when not in use. All equipment works this way. When one
has mastery of his tools, and uses them in a familiar or comfortable setting,
the tools fade, or in other words, just by beholding equipment, one looses
thematic awareness of the entity in use. The ready-to-hand is inconspicuous.
In moments of breakdown the
ready-to-hand allows Heidegger to uncover three intermediate modes of being:
conspicuousness (unready-to-hand, when something breaks), obtrusiveness (when
something goes missing), and obstinacy (when another concern diverts our
attention away from our dealings with the ready-to-hand). These modes signify
when the ready-to-hand becomes unusable.
When an entity is needed, but is missing our awareness is heightened and
focused on the absence. This is one way in which the world “lights” up to
Dasein. By investigating these intermediate modes of being, one is able to
notice an entities relation to the equipmental whole. The ready-to-hand becomes
unready-to-hand (an intermediate mode of being, where the tool is still seen as
a tool, but one is aware of its
connections and properties, how the tool is connected to the world). Whereas the
ready-to-hand usually withdraws, a damaged unready-to-hand tool is in need of
repair. One must know a tool's “in order to” in order to fix it. Once a tool is repaired, one inevitably views
the object as withdrawn and ready-to-hand.
When philosophers analyze the present-at-hand, they aren't capturing the way the world really is. “Theoretical behavior is just looking, without circumspection” (BT 99/70). In contrast to the present-at-hand, Heidegger coins the term ready-to-hand, which he believes is the real mode in which the vast majority of equipment functions in Dasein's everyday experience. When entities are ready-to-hand, they withdraw from one's awareness. If one wants to study an entity, one must stop using it, remove it from its totality, and put it on the observation table. At this point, though, Dasein is acting in a fundamentally different manner, or mode of Being; Dasein is in a theoretical observation mode. When Dasein switches over to that mode, the ready-at-hand entities to be examined change over into a present-at-hand object. The entities become inert and sit there.
Philosophy must operate at this level because, by definition, it is a matter of thinking and examining. The manner in which we examine an entity changes the the very entity we examine. One cannot stare at and study a ready-to-hand tool because as soon as it look at it in this mode, the tool ceases to be a tool. The experience of the drill in a carpenter's hand as he is drilling, when he is not focusing on it at all (routine action) is completely different from simply staring at it. Philosophers attempt to examine nature as it really is, but the way they examine the world changes the reality which is being examined -- it must necessarily deprive itself of the ready-to-hand. The tools only are what they are during use, but that is when we cannot have thematic awareness. As soon as we start paying attention to the tools they stop being what they are.
When this
happens the ready-to-hand equipment changes its mode of being. The
ready-to-hand becomes unready-to-hand (an intermediate mode of being, where the
tool is still seen as a tool, but one is aware of its connections and properties, how the tool
is connected to the world). Whereas the ready-to-hand usually withdraws, a
damaged unready-to-hand tool is in need of repair. One must know a tool's “in
order to” in order to fix it. Once a
tool is repaired, one inevitably views the object as withdrawn and
ready-to-hand.
One quickly
notices that Heidegger does not talk about subjects or minds, but of Dasein and
its interconnectedness to the world. The world and Dasein are a unified whole,
both are inseparably merged together. When one is playing baseball, for
example, it is almost as if the glove is indistinguishable from Dasein. In the
experience of catching the ball, one does not think of the glove as an entity
apart from the body, but as an extension of the whole. Equipment and Dasein
come together forming an undifferentiated mass, the experience of playing
baseball. Heidegger's approach is holistic. Dasein does not come across
individual entities when engaged in its dealings. Phenomenologically the
totality comes first metaphysically and experientially. Entities could not be
the equipment they are without being seen in connection and conjunction with
the whole of the Being of the totality of the world. Dasein does not perceive
entities individually, but as a whole. Heidegger argues that, “there 'is' no
such thing as an equipment. To the Being of any equipment there always
belongs a totality of equipment, in which it can be this equipment that it is”
(BT 97/69). There can never be a piece of equipment totally isolated, torn from
its relation to the totality of other equipment. To illustrate this concept, it
is useful to think of a steel mill: miles of equipment cooperating and meshing
together, being used by workers who create the commodity steel. All of the
entities in the mill belong together. A centrifugal roll sleeve caster would be
inconceivable – indeed, its purpose would be rendered incoherent -- without the totality of other associated
machinery used in steel production.
Dasein
ascribes certain normative roles, functions, and behaviors to equipment.
Equipment can be used incorrectly; for example, one would not use an axle
assembly line to produce yarn, nor could a spinning jenny be used to produce
tires. Dasein builds tools whose behavior fits the purpose of the tool. A
bucket is used to carry liquids or other materials, not to stir a bowl of soup.
The
“towards-which” signifies a mode of Being which an entity or Dasein moves
towards, its aim and direction (not in a traditional spatial sense). For
instance, the towards-which of a shovel is to dig a ditch, a piano to produce
sound. The “towards-which” of a specific Dasein might be to become a well-known
composer. Everything that exists must have something which it aims at, that it
moves towards. The “towards-which” always has an anatomy, structure, or design
of this mode of being. The spinning
jenny's “towards-which” is to transform wool into yarn; the yarn, in turn, will
be turned a coat, which is equipment for Dasein. The “towards-which” has the
same mode of being as the thing producing it; it is merely a tool used in
making another tool. The “towards-which” is also ready-to-hand.
We can only
do this in the context of activities and equipment. Dasein is a manifesting of
sorts; Dasein lives its way of being in
tools or equipment. Being-in-the-world, one is in the world by performing or
embodying certain roles. The world is just the totalities of all of these
chains of equipment. The worldhood is chains of use. One gets absorbed into
these. Dasein is absorbed into the world, like ink into a blotter. The ink is
still there, but it is in the fabric of the blotter or cloth.
Works cited:
Comments
Post a Comment